Jeremy Bentham on Utilitarianism.
As
a Utilitarian, Bentham felt that humanity naturally seeks to maximise
pleasure/happiness. That is to say pleasure or happiness as the individual
perceives it, rather than an Aristotelian or Platoian definition, which Bentham
thought unnecessary.
Bentham,
rather than concentrating on the meaning of the terms used, sought to discover
how we decide which pleasure to choose and how we assign merit to each. From
this research, Bentham came to the conclusion that individuals apply, what he
called, the ‘felicific calculus’.
Felicific
calculus involves analysing the potential intensity, length, certainty and
immediacy of pleasure or pain created by each choice. However, this internal
calculation doesn’t end there; once we have analysed the characteristics of the
aforementioned pleasure or pain, we also judge the fecundity and purity of a
pleasure.
Fecundity
is the analysis of the potential of a subsequent series of pleasures following
the initial decision, an example of which being attendance in further
education, as we go with the intention social and educational experience that
should cause pleasure. However, the acquisition of a degree will also mean an
increase in employment options as well as potentially leading to a higher
salary.
The
purity of a pleasure is measured through the likelihood that the initial
pleasure will be subsequently followed by a series of pains. A good example of
which being the partaking in intercourse, which could lead to the contraction
of a sexually transmitted disease. Therefore, a pure pleasure is one without
any negative consequences.
Whilst
an individual uses the felicific calculus to analyse the potential pleasure of
a decision or action, in order to apply this to politics or society, we must
use what Bentham calls ‘extension’. Simply put, extension is taking into
account the potential pain or pleasure caused by an action, but on a larger
scale, so a government uses extension when contemplating change in national
law, anticipating the effect it will have upon the population as a whole.
Flaws in Bentham’s system.
‘The
greatest happiness of the greatest number’ is an evocative phrase, but it is
ambiguous (unless by ‘number’ it’s meaning is to consider all those affected by
an action). ‘The greatest number’ of what?
Utilitarian’s since Bentham have been divided. It is likely that Bentham would
have said that it is the greatest number of human beings, although most modern
utilitarian philosophers would now consider animals as having the right to be
included. An example of which being recent animal rights laws and charities
such as the RSPCA.
The
consideration of animal welfare seems appropriate under Bentham’s system, as
the sensation of experiencing pain and pleasure is the main moral criteria
considered and science has shown that animals do indeed feel pleasure and pain,
so it seems that animals are facilitated by the theory. Although Bentham
rejected the idea of animal rights.
Another
question that can be raised is who should control this system? Although the
answer is a matter of opinion based more on politics than ethics. That being
said, the current control is the monetary system, with those of a wealthier
nation or upbringing receiving the highest potential for pleasure.
Beyond
this, if an individual is bound to serve their own happiness, how can anyone be
expected to maintain the extended ramifications? Theoretically democracy should
fill this void, by bringing together the individual felicific calculus’ to find
a solution to better suit everyone, however, in modern society this continues
to prove difficult for humanity.
John Stuart Mill.
Mill
agreed with criticisms of Bentham, that making decisions entirely based upon
pleasure is animalistic , however, Mill then argued that humanities ability to
differentiate and rank pains and pleasures as well as predicting the
consequences of actions is what ultimately separates the Utilitarian ideal from
being animalistic.
Mill
also states that dignity has an effect upon our happiness, due to a lack of
appreciation for most pleasures if our dignity is taken. Although, whether or
not dignity is merely a label for a complexity of actions causing a specific
form of happiness.
Schopenhauer on the Will and Renunciation.
Schopenhauer’s
‘The world as Will and Representation’ sees the individual as only individual
in their perception of the Will or everything in and of itself, but states that
we are still under the influence of the Will in our actions.
Schopenhauer
believed that our free will is an illusion. We think ourselves free to choose
on the basis that we unknowingly come across decisions, yet Schopenhauer states
that this is merely that our perception, limited within time, cannot understand
the infinite perception of the Will.
Schopenhauer
expands on this in relation to the individual character:
Intelligible
character: This is Schopenhauer’s ‘reality’ – the infinite portion of
ourselves, directly linked with the Will and in complete control of our
actions.
Empirical
character: The part of us that analyses our living experience of the Will.
Acquired
character: A part of the self, only reclaimed through the renunciation of our
desire to live. The Acquired character must be learned through the
understanding of the individual nature and limitations, tailoring their
ambitions accordingly.
Schopenhauer
believes that there is no escape from the Will, only an increased understanding
of it through the development of Acquired character.
Schopenhauer
also defines good and bad people:
The
good man: Recognises others’ Will to live, but not their own.
The
bad man: Recognises only their own Will.
The
just man: Individuality doesn’t partition them from others, they recognise
their own Will on the same level as others’.
Nietzsche and the Transvaluation of Values.
Nietzsche
saw the call to Christianity as without reason, but unlike Kierkegaard (‘So
much the worse for mere reason’), Nietzsche saw reason as the enlightening
path: ‘so much the worse for the call to Christianity’. He saw Christianity as
the rebellion of the lower classes, turning the aristocratic stereotype that
they were vulgar, cowardly and untruthful and turning it on its head, setting
up their own value system valuing traits such as humility, sympathy and
benevolence, which benefit them. Christianity in Nietzsche’s view, sought to
set the aristocracy as characteristically bad. Nietzsche said that Christianity
put itself forward as a religion of love , yet it was based in weakness, fear
and malice. However, he felt that the strongest characteristic was ‘ressentiment’
which he defined as the desire of the weak to take revenge on the strong, but
they disguised this as a wish to punish the sinner. Even in exalting
compassion, Nietzsche believes that they are exerting power over them.
Nietzsche
thought Christianity was so sinister that it degraded the human race through humiliating sufferers through pity;
infecting a compassionate person with the suffering of others. From this,
Nietzsche felt that we should allow the weak to perish so that they, or
humanity might better themselves. It is these theories and his close
relationship with Wagner that has caused critics to affiliate him with Nazi
Germany.
Likening
to a later Karl Marx, Nietzsche applied a Hegelian dialectic, with master and slave
forming the thesis and antithesis to form a superhuman or Ubermensch. These
supermen would become the next stage in humanity.
‘Humanity
is something that must be surpassed: man is a bridge and not a goal’.
Analytic Ethics.
Opposed
to Nietzsche, G.E.Moore’s Principia
Ethica (1903) doesn’t see ethics as involving the development of the
species, and sees good as the topic of ethics. How is good to be defined?
Before we can act, we must define good, and it is good that we must try to
create in abundance according to Moore.
The
naturalistic fallacy was confusing good as a natural property. Nor is it to be
associated with pleasantness; however it can be a property of natural things. Moore believed that the only non-natural things
that were intrinsically linked with good were friendship and aesthetic
experience.
Moore’s
work was influential with the Bloomsbury group, in particular; Keynes, Lytton
Strachey and F.M. Forster. They thought of Principia Ethica as a charter for
lifestyle, throwing away the norm of respectability and rectitude.
However,
the rise of Logical Positivism meant that philosophers doubted and even denied
‘good’ as a property at all. A.J. Ayer said that ‘Stealing money is wrong’
holds no factual meaning, as it is neither true nor false. It is instead an
expression of their individual moral disapproval.
R.M.
Hare wanted ethics to be included in logic, believing that there is logic of
imperatives no less than a logic of assertion. Hare distinguished between
prescriptive and descriptive meaning:
Prescriptive
statement: telling oneself or another, often in conjunction with a descriptive
statement, what they ought to do based upon moral inclination.
Descriptive
statement: One relying upon factual conditions in order to be true.
Like
Hume, Hare was of the opinion that you cannot derive an ought from an is. He
sought to distinguish ethics from morals; ethics being the study of morals, and
morals actions based upon ones ethics. However, Hare is overly concerned with
the way in which we define the term ‘good’. We apply good with different
meaning in different contexts, so attempting to pin a singular meaning to it is
futile.
No comments:
Post a Comment